vendredi 11 novembre 2011

Les concepts de nature. Chine-Europe, une perspective transculturelle / Augustin Berque


Birds and flowers, detail from a horizontal scroll (Chao Chi)
Birds and flowers, detail from a horizontal scroll (Chao Chi)
Pour East Asian Science, Technology and Medicine, Tübingen.

Review of  Concepts of nature.
A Chinese-European cross cultural perspective
edited by Hans Ulrich Vogel & Günter Dux
with an overview and introduction by Mark Elvin,
Leiden.Boston : Brill, 2010, 566 p.


As recall the acknowledgments, "this volume originated in a conference on 'Understanding Nature in China and Europe until the Eighteenth Century: a Cross-Cultural Project', held in the city of Rheine in Westphalia, Germany, from March 22 to 25, 2000" (p. vii). It gathers a total of 17 articles by 15 authors, under the editorship of a sinologist (Hans Ulrich Vogel, University of Tübingen) and a philosopher and sociologist (Günter Dux, University of Freiburg), with a considerable help from another sinologist : Mark Elvin (Australian National University at Canberra), who wrote a substantial overview of the whole set (p. 1-55) and a synopsis of each contribution (p. 56-101). Adding his own chapter (p. 400-468), this is to say that Elvin alone wrote about nearly one third of this huge collective work.  

The themes addressed by the book are the following: "The genesis of philosophy in the history of mind: a cross-cultural comparison between classical Greece and China" (Günter Dux); "The universe as cosmos: on the ontology of the Greek world image" (Julián Pacho); "The notion of causality in Aristotle and the medieval philosophy of nature: a developmental approach" (Ulrich Vogel);  "Cosmology and concepts of nature in traditional China" (John B. Anderson); "On nature and culture in Zhou China" (Heiner Roetz); "Towards a conceptual history of some concepts of nature in classical Chinese: zi ran自然and zi ran zhi li自然之理" (Christoph Harbsmeier); "Mathematics, nature and cosmological inquiry in traditional China" (Karine Chemla); "When Shen Gua encountered the 'natural world': a preliminary discussion on the Mengxi bitan and the concept of nature" (Fu Daiwie); "Becoming acquainted with nature from the Odes: sidelights on the study of flora and fauna in Song dynasty's Shijing 詩経 (Classic of Odes) scholarship" (Achim Mittag); "Concepts of nature in traditional Chinese materia medica and botany  (sixteenth to seventeenth century)" (Georges Métailié); "The investigation of things (gewu 格物), natural studies (gezhixue 格致学), and evidental studies (kaozhengxue 考証学) in late imperial China (1600-1800") (Benjamin A. Elman); "Personal luck: why premodern China - probably - did not develop probabilistic thinking" (Mark Elvin); "'That which soaks and descends becomes salty': the concept of nature in traditional Chinese salt production" (Hans Ulrich Vogel); "The myriad things: random thoughts on nature in China and the West" (Wolfgang Kubin); "On the relationship between man and nature in China" (Helwig Schmidt-Glinzer).
Needless to say, discussing all this variegated, and often extremely detailed material is beyond the scope of a single book review. I will concentrate myself on some general ideas. First of all, let us render thanks to the three editors for having gathered and organized such a rich amount of reflexions on the cross-cultural analysis of the concept of nature. There have been in the last quarter of a century or so many international conferences comparing the conceptions of nature (自然観) in the East and in the West, but seldom has the matter so methodically been explored.  This is without doubt a reference book on the question of nature in China (clearly more than in Europe), both for its texts and for the huge amount of bibliography ending most of the chapters (e.g. 136 titles in Vogel's one).
 Let us also thank Elvin for having written an equitable synthesis of all that material, overcoming the inevitable discrepancies between nearly a score of different points view on, and approaches of basically the same question, many of which are highly technical (greatly so Elvin's own study on probability).  This spares me the venture of trying to do the same.  I will rather discuss the few following points, which in my mind are decisive ones.
First of all, having chosen a historical period ending in the eighteenth century intends of course to limit the question within those times when the European mode of relating to nature had not yet overwhelmed, in the form of the industrialized world, all the other modes, including the traditional European ones. Before the industrial revolution, indeed, China and Europe might be compared more fairly, and as is well known, this comparison might advantage China more often than the reverse. Accordingly, for the sake of comparison, there a good reasons for having excluded the 19th and 20th centuries. Yet, what had been going on before 1800 is precisely that which explains what happened later. This is particularly the case of the scientific revolution, which happened in Europe in the 17th century, and without which - at least in my mind - the industrial revolution would not have been possible.
This is certainly a controversial point. On that point, the book does not delve systematically enough into the debate. For sure, many of the articles give us precious clues of the lack of a really scientific (in the modern Western sense) approach of natural phenomena in China; this is, for example, clearly expressed by the very title of Vogel's article. Yet, this does not amount to a direct discussion. On the whole, this lack of a direct appraisal of the scientific revolution reminds one of Kenneth Pommeranz' The Great Divergence: China, Europe and the making of the modern world economy (Princeton University Press, 2000), the interpretation of which might easily let one think that, after all, the industrial revolution could be explained without the factor of modern science.
As said above, I do not agree with that view. This is not for the only reason that what has become technoscience is nowadays  inherent to industry, but rather because modern science and industry both stem from the same conception of nature as an object; and this is precisely the paradigm which the scientific revolution definitely established.    
This exceeds the question of defining what the modern scientific method properly is; it rather becomes an ontological and logical problem, and in this respect, what is peculiar is the European historical path, not the Chinese one.  What the Chinese have known about nature has a common decisive trait  with India, the Arab world or Europe before the Galilean-Newtonian paradigm: this knowledge did not leave aside human existence. This is what expresses the notion of cosmos, that is, a comprehensive order including both nature and the human. Of course, each culture expresses this common condition (viz cosmicity) in its proper terms. Much of the contents of Concepts of nature show that, in various ways, the Chinese view of nature has kept an analogical or correlative bent, reflecting  the human on the natural. Even though the systematic correlations established by Dong Zhongshu under the Han dynasty between natural and social facts may have been discussed later (resulting in a progressively more profane worldview, as show several of the articles), physics never became independent from political and moral considerations. Now, this is precisely what happened in modern Europe - at least in principle -, not elsewhere.
The said principle is nothing else than dualism, which simultaneously absolutized the object (the res extensa) on the one hand, and the subject (the res cogitans) on the other hand. This radically abstracted the human subject out of nature, which became, by the same token, a pure object. As Descartes wrote in the Discours de la méthode,  the cogito exists in itself : "(...) I knew then that I was a substance (...) which, in order to be, does not need any place (n'a besoin d'aucun lieu) (...)".
As one of the articles recalls (Fu, p. 306), it may indeed be contested, like Bruno Latour did in his controversial Nous n'avons jamais été modernes (We have never been modern, Harvard: Harvester Wheatsheah, 1993), that modern dualism ever existed. In my mind, this thesis amounts to confusing what Plato distinguished, an ideal paradigm on the one hand, and actual practice on the other hand. Now, this distinction is precisely what, much later, made the scientific revolution possible; and this is because paradigms are that which leads practice in a certain historical direction. That is also what happened with modern dualism as a paradigm : it has entailed such historical phenomena as the industrial revolution, although no modern scientist, might he be Galileo or Newton, ever actualized in his practice the cogito's ideal abstraction. Newton in his practice as a historical person never transcended the contingencies of concrete space (which is heterogeneous, anisotropic and limited by a horizon), although his physics postulates an absolute, homogeneous, isotropic and infinite space. It may then be that Newton was not modern, but the principles of his cosmology indeed were, and that is what historically proved to be important. It later entailed, for example, the abstraction of "universal space" in architecture.
Now, both absolute space or time presuppose dualism. Without this condition, both remain related to human existence. Dualism in its turn presupposes logically the law of the excluded middle : either the subject (A) or the object (non-A), but no intermediate entity, which would be both A and non-A. Western logic, from Aristotle to Hegel and beyond until Lupasco, has clinged to this law (Hegel's synthesis overcomes the contradiction of the thesis and the antithesis, it does not make them coexist). Several chapters in Concepts of nature deal with Aristotle, but none with this question. Now, it is a decisive one, because the law of the excluded middle did not only entail dualism; it forcludes (locks out) symbolicity, a symbol being precisely that which makes A and non-A coexist in one and the same thing. This forclusion of symbolicity has been inherent to Western rationalism at least since Plato's Republic, from which the poets - in other words mythical thought - are banned because "reason made that a duty for us" (ho gar logos hêmas hêrei, I, VIII, 609 b 3).
In China, contrary to Europe, the most elaborate form of logic - that of Buddhism -  not only did not exclude the middle, it explicitly included it in the form of the Nagarjunian tetralemma : 1) affirmation (A); 2) negation (non-A); 3) neither affirmation nor negation (neither A nor non-A); 4) both affirmation and negation (both A and non-A). Particularly in Zen (Chan) Buddhism, this form of logic is also known, in Suzuki Daisetz 鈴木大拙 's terms, as the "logic of sokuhi" (即非の論理). This may sound exotic, but it is in fact the very logic of symbolicity. Indeed, what the fourth lemma expresses is nothing else than what a symbol concretely embodies: the principle of the included middle, at the same time A and non-A.
Now, the human being a zôon logon echôn (a living who possesses language), a human world is necessarily fraught with symbolicity. That is what the Greeks called kosmos, the Romans mundus, and the Chinese yuzhou 宇宙. Reversely, what the law of the exluded middle and its forclusion of symbolicity eventually entailed, in the form of modern dualism and mechanicism, is a universe alien to human existence - that universe about which Pascal wrote "the eternal silence of these infinite spaces frightens me (le silence éternel de ces espaces infinis m'effraie)". And the reason why this universe, born from the scientific revolution, never appeared in China until brought in from the industrialized West, is fundamentally that Chinese reason did not ban poets and symbols.    
There is not much about Buddhism in Concepts of Nature, and nothing about tetralemmas. To be sure, there are some developments about logic, especially so in Dux' article, which puts forward, concerning China, a "subjectivistic logic". However, this article remains ambiguous about what means the very word "subject". A subject in logic (S : 主題 or 主語) is opposed to a predicate (P : 述語); it is not opposed to an object (O : 客体 or 対象). On the contrary, what for the logician is the subject is precisely that which for the physicist is the object, i.e. that which the problem is about. Dux does not make this distinction, nor is he concerned with predicates. Now, reality, be it in a human or in an animal world, is the way a subject (in the psychological sense, i.e. a certain being) interprets an object (i.e. a subject in the logical sense, S) by dint of some predicate (P); that is, puts it within a certain category (in Aristotle's terms, a predicate is a katêgorêma). In other words, S is taken as P, through the subject's senses, thoughts, words or action; and reality amounts to the relation S/P.
 Now, Aristotelian logic is based on the identity of S, in which it is linked with the law of the excluded middle. This is also why modern dualism could absolutize the subject's consciousness (the cogito) on the one hand, and the object on the other hand: they are two different substantial S, one being A and the other one non-A, with their respective identities. If one follows Dux' expression, this might be called an "objectivistic logic", as opposed to the "subjectivistic" Chinese one. Yet in fact, there is not much objectiveness in that dualistic absolutization of S ; because in reality (S/P), there can exist no S unless taken (predicated) as some P by a certain being. A pure S is a pure abstraction. And it is exactly such an abstraction which the modern Western  scientific paradigm amounts to. 
In contradistinction, the Chinese logic appears as a logic of concreteness, that of a world actually inhabited by human beings, who feel, think, speak and act about the objects (S) in a certain way (P), making them real things (S/P). This logic, out of the universe (S), makes a cosmos (S/P), which speaks through symbols to the people's mind. It differs from those "eternally mute and infinite spaces" which were born from the scientific revolution. In other words, the Chinese did not decosmize their world, as with their respective world did the Europeans - at least paradigmatically, yet entailing in the long run tremendous practical effects. This process is what Heidegger has called Entweltlichung, "deworldlization", adding that this gave rise to "Natur" (as an object). It goes without saying that the Chinese ziran 自然, zaohua 造化and the like (Harbmeier's article is particularly enlightening about this terminology) did not become such a "Natur".
As Concepts of Nature does not pay much attention to Heideggerian phraseology, let us put this in a more precise way. What the process of decosmization means is that modern dualism has, at least in principle, reduced our ambient world or milieu (Umwelt, in Uexküll's vocabulary) to an objective environment (or Umgebung). At about the same time when Uexküll, dealing in Germany with animals in general, established this essential distinction between Umgebung (which exists only for the scientist) and Umwelt (which is reality for any living being, and is always specific to that being, e.g. proper  to a certain animal species), Watsuji, in Japan, established a strictly homologous distinction between shizen kankyô自然環境 (the natural environment, as objectified by the natural sciences) and fûdo 風土, i.e. the milieu proper to a given society.
Here and there, in Concepts of Nature, one can catch a glimpse of that essential difference between environment and milieu, or Umgebung and Umwelt; but it is not systematized, nor even explicitly addressed.  For example, Kubin is perfectly right when he writes (p. 522), "I do not differentiate between nature and landscape in the Chinese context". By the way, he might have added that one should not differentiate between nature and fengshui (a topic not addressed by the book, though eminently distinctive of the Chinese conception of the natural environment). This means, in fact, that in China, the environment was not reduced to the Umgebung; it remained a milieu (an Umwelt). Or, to put it logically, reality remained a concrete S/P, it was not decomposed into two dualistic abstractions, A (a certain S, in this case the res cogitans) and non-A (another S, in this case the res extensa), forcluding (locking out) the fact that human existence necessarily predicates the environment (S) into a milieu (S/P), and that reducing S/P to S (i.e. the milieu to an objective Umgebung) amounts not only to decosmize, but to dehumanize the environment. 
If I have here insisted on these logical and ontological aspects of the question of nature, it is, needless to say, because I should have liked the book to establish more firmly these general and structuring aspects of the human relationship with the environment. Be it as it may, Concepts of Nature is an extremely rich source of detailed information, enabling one to elaborate that very problematics in its historical actualization. After reading the book, one has plenty of concrete illustrations at one's disposal, showing the respective merits and demerits of keeping nature as an appropriate cosmos, or of changing it into an alien, indifferent universe. In that sense, Concepts of Nature, though ending before the industrial revolution, has much to teach us about our present environmental crisis, and gives us many hints about the ways to overcome it.   

Augustin BERQUE
berque@ehess.fr
8 Nov 2011  

    
Aperçu de l'ouvrage :